Commentary
Article
Author(s):
A final argument on psychiatric diagnoses.
This article is a response to the article “Will Denial Make DSM’s Validity Problem Go Away? A Reply to Pies and Ruffalo” by Jani Kajanoja, MD, PhD, and Jussi Valtonen, PhD.
“A map is not the territory it represents, but if correct, it has a similar structure to the territory, which accounts for its usefulness.”-Alfred Korzybski1
We appreciate the latest rejoinder from Jani Kajanoja, MD, PhD, and Jussi Valtonen, PhD, (Drs K & V) in this ongoing exchange.2 Let us all agree that there are serious problems with the DSM categories and the entire categorical approach to diagnosis; that many of the DSM conditions have low or marginal inter-rater reliability (kappa)—including major depressive disorder—and that the vast majority do not have specific biological validators.3 There is nothing new or startling in these observations, which were never the focus of our initial rejoinder4; namely, our objection to K & V’s broad-brush claim that psychiatric diagnoses are little more than a repackaging of the patient’s presenting signs and symptoms, with no explanatory value and no causal relationship to these presenting features.5
We also acknowledge that “disease,” “disorder,” “illness,” etc are complex and contested terms that remain areas of controversy in the philosophy of psychiatry literature, and that there are compelling arguments in favor of noncategorical/alternative diagnostic systems in psychiatry.6 There is also controversy surrounding the complex concepts of “causality,” “natural kinds, “diagnostic kinds,” “practical kinds,” and other essentially metaphysical issues, which are best dealt with in journals specializing in the philosophy of science and psychiatry.7,8 However, we will draw upon psychologist Peter Zachar, PhD’s concept of “practical kinds” as they relate to psychiatric categories.9,10
Notwithstanding these complexities, we have argued that several of the most serious diagnoses in psychiatry—such as bipolar disorder, schizophrenia, obsessive-compulsive disorder (OCD), and anorexia nervosa—have considerable explanatory value and validity. Furthermore, conceptualizing them as causes of the patient’s signs and symptoms can be substantively informative—even though we do not yet know the precise causes of these illnesses. For example, it is clinically useful and informative to say that a patient is experiencing fatigue and impaired concentration because they are depressed—and not because of, say, a viral infection. We find nothing in K & V’s latest rejoinder that seriously impugns this assertion. [see footnote].
Historically, Kraepelin considered schizophrenia (dementia praecox) and bipolar disorder (manic-depressive illness) to be disease processes (Krankheitsprozessen), as contrasted with clinical pictures (Zustandsbilden).3,11 Kraepelin almost certainly regarded these disease processes as causes of their associated signs and symptoms—eg, he believed that “…dementia praecox causes a breaking-down of the self…”12
And while our goal was never to sing the praises of the DSM-5 or its latest revision, we have repeatedly pointed out that the correct use of this manual requires much more than simply matching the patient’s signs and symptoms to those of a DSM category; rather, the manual explicitly requires that the coded diagnosis must be supported by a biopsychosocial case formulation of the patient’s presenting problem. This critical point is conspicuously unacknowledged in both of K & V’s rejoinders.
With that prologue, we now point out some specific areas of disagreement with Drs K & V:
“…can help them have a better understanding of themselves…and their symptoms. It can provide validation, and knowledge that some symptoms may relate to their diagnosis and not them as a person…[diagnosis] may provide reassurance that the individual’s situation is not unique, mysterious or inexplicable… [and] can reduce stigma by explicitly acknowledging the presence of illness.”36
Indeed, over the course of more than 25 years, one of us (RP) witnessed many instances in which a patient newly-diagnosed with bipolar 1 disorder expressed great relief at finally having received an explanation for years of severe mood swings—and many found their lives vastly improved with lithium treatment.37
Concluding Thoughts
We have acknowledged the drawbacks of categorical diagnostic systems, such as the DSM and ICD. We also acknowledge the controversies surrounding the ontological status—the “is-ness”—of psychiatric disorders and the complex nature of “causality.” But to deny the reality of serious psychiatric illness—or to trivialize it as mere “psychological distress”—is to do a great disservice to those who entrust us with their care. It seems to us equally unhelpful to deny that psychiatric disorders cause the symptoms identified in their diagnostic criteria—which merely point to, and do not fully capture or define, the underlying psychophysical condition.
Indeed, as the Table shows,38-44 the ordinary language of mental health care attributes causality to many of our diagnostic categories. We believe the burden of proof rests with Drs K & V to show why—collectively and individually—all these sources are misguided in their use of the term, “cause”. To recall Wittgenstein’s maxim: “Ordinary language is alright.”45 And in our view, there is much to be said for common usage and common sense!
We have enjoyed these exchanges and are happy to give the last word to our Finnish colleagues, should they wish it.
Acknowledgments: The authors wish to thank Drs Kenneth Schaffner and Peter Zachar for their comments on some aspects of this debate. However, the views presented here are solely those of the authors, unless otherwise noted.
Footnote: When we say, for example, that schizophrenia "causes" auditory hallucinations and paranoid delusions, we are not positing a mechanical kind of causality, akin to how billiard ball A collides with billiard ball B, causing it to move into the side pocket. (Of course, the philosopher David Hume famously noted that we do not actually "see" causality in this scenario—only the temporal sequence of events). Rather, we are hypothesizing (not “assuming”) that a recognizable and characteristic psychophysiological state—the product of innumerable antecedent biological, psychological, and social factors—is responsible for the patient's signs and symptoms. That is, we hypothesize that the term "schizophrenia" (as a practical kind) points to a characteristic pathological condition of the human mind that is responsible for the symptoms we call "schizophrenic." One type of causal reasoning expresses this idea as a counterfactual statement; ie, "If Smith did not have schizophrenia (or a related condition), he would not be experiencing auditory hallucinations and paranoid delusions." We may justifiably posit this type of causation without necessarily knowing the pathophysiology of schizophrenia.
Dr Pies is Professor Emeritus of Psychiatry and Lecturer on Bioethics and Humanities, SUNY Upstate Medical University; Clinical Professor of Psychiatry Emeritus, Tufts University School of Medicine; and Editor in Chief Emeritus of Psychiatric Times (2007-2010). Dr Pies is the author of several books. A collection of his works can be found on Amazon. Dr Ruffalo is an assistant professor of psychiatry at the University of Central Florida College of Medicine in Orlando and adjunct instructor of psychiatry at Tufts University School of Medicine in Boston, Massachusetts.
References
1. Korzybski A. Science and Sanity: An Introduction to Non-Aristotelian Systems and General Semantics. 5th edition. Institute of General Semantics; 1995.
2. Valtonen J, Kajanoja J. Will denial make DSM’s validity problem go away? A reply to Pies and Ruffalo. Psychiatric Times. October 14, 2024. https://www.psychiatrictimes.com/view/will-denial-make-dsms-validity-problem-go-away-a-reply-to-pies-and-ruffalo
3. Ghaemi SN. Taking disease seriously in DSM. World Psychiatry. 2013;12(3):210-212.
4. Pies RW, Ruffalo ML. No, psychiatric diagnoses do not reflect “circular logic.” Psychiatric Times. June 26, 2024. https://www.psychiatrictimes.com/view/no-psychiatric-diagnoses-do-not-reflect-circular-logic
5. Kajanoja J, Valtonen J. A descriptive diagnosis or a causal explanation? Accuracy of depictions of depression on authoritative health organization websites. Psychopathology. 2024;57(5):389-398.
6. Zachar P, Kendler KS. The philosophy of nosology. Annu Rev Clin Psychol. 2017;13:49-71.
7. Aftab A. Definitional circularity and context dependence.Psychiatry at the Margins. October 13, 2024. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.psychiatrymargins.com/p/definitional-circularity-and-context
8. Tabb K. Philosophy of psychiatry after diagnostic kinds. Synthese. 2019;196(6):2177-2195.
9. Zachar P. Psychiatric disorders are not natural kinds. PPP. 2000;7(3):167-182.
10. Zachar P. Psychiatric disorders: natural kinds made by the world or practical kinds made by us? World Psychiatry. 2015;14(3):288-290.
11. Boestrom A. Zustandsbild und krankheit in der psychiatrie. Klinische Wochenschrift. 1923;2:1728-1731.
12. Kircher T, David A. The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry. Cambridge University Press; 2003.
13. Bird A, Tobin E. Natural kinds. In: Zalta EN, Nodelman U, eds. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; 2024.
14. Pies RW. How Avicenna recognized melancholia and mixed states—1000 years before modern psychiatry. Psychiatric Times. September 22, 2020. https://www.psychiatrictimes.com/view/how-avicenna-recognized-melancholia-mixed-states-1000-years-before-modern-psychiatry
15. Kendler KS. The nature of psychiatric disorders. World Psychiatry. 2016;15(1):5-12.
16. Pies R. On myths and countermyths: more on Szaszian fallacies. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1979;36(2):139-144.
17. Starling A. Migraine. Mayo Clinic Explains. July 7, 2023. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.mayoclinic.org/diseases-conditions/migraine-headache/symptoms-causes/syc-20360201
18. Benoliel R, Gaul C. Persistent idiopathic facial pain. Cephalalgia. 2017;37(7):680-691.
19. Wilner A. Personal communication. September 11, 2024.
20. Pies R. Toward a concept of instrumental validity: implications for psychiatric diagnosis. crossing dialogues. Dial Phil Ment Neuro Sci. 2011;4(1):18-19.
21. Pies RW. Science, psychiatry, and family practice: positivism vs. pluralism. Psychiatric Times. October 14, 2013. https://www.psychiatrictimes.com/view/science-psychiatry-and-family-practice-positivism-vs-pluralism
22. Luvsannyam E, Jain MS, Pormento MKL, et al. Neurobiology of schizophrenia: a comprehensive review. Cureus. 2022;14(4):e23959.
23. Scaini G, Valvassori SS, Diaz AP, et al. Neurobiology of bipolar disorders: a review of genetic components, signaling pathways, biochemical changes, and neuroimaging findings. Braz J Psychiatry. 2020;42(5):536-551.
24. Mason P, Harrison G, Croudace T, et al. The predictive validity of a diagnosis of schizophrenia: a report from the International Study of Schizophrenia (ISoS) coordinated by the World Health Organization and the Department of Psychiatry, University of Nottingham. Br J Psychiatry. 1997;170:321-327.
25. Hollis C. Adult outcomes of child- and adolescent-onset schizophrenia: diagnostic stability and predictive validity. Am J Psychiatry. 2000;157(10):1652-1659.
26. Cirone C, Secci I, Favole I, et al. What do we know about the long-term course of early onset bipolar disorder? A review of the current evidence. Brain Sci. 2021;11(3):341.
27. Schmideberg M. The borderline patient. In: Arieti S, ed. The American Handbook of Psychiatry. Vol 1. Basic Books; 1959:398-416.
28. Bohus M, Stoffers-Winterling J, Sharp C, et al. Borderline personality disorder. Lancet. 2021;398(10310):1528-1540.
29. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, 5th edition. American Psychiatric Association; 2013
30. Schaffner KF. Variation and validation: the example of schizophrenia. World Psychiatry. 2016;15(1):39-40.
31. Arieti S. Recent conceptions and misconceptions of schizophrenia. Am J Psychother. 1960;14:3-29.
32. American Medical Association classifies obesity as a disease. Health Letter. November 1, 2013. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.citizen.org/news/american-medical-association-classifies-obesity-as-a-disease/
33. Committee on the Assessment of Ongoing Effects in the Treatment of Posttraumatic Stress Disorder; Institute of Medicine. Treatment for Posttraumatic Stress Disorder in Military and Veteran Populations: Initial Assessment. National Academies Press; 2012.
34. Hinton DE, Lewis-Fernández R. The cross-cultural validity of posttraumatic stress disorder: implications for DSM-5. Depress Anxiety. 2011;28(9):783-801.
35. Pies RW. What should count as a mental disorder in DSM-V? Psychiatric Times. April 14, 2009. https://www.psychiatrictimes.com/view/what-should-count-mental-disorder-dsm-v
36. Munro M. Mental health diagnosis: looking at a grey area through a critical lens. Nursing Times. September 20, 2021. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.nursingtimes.net/roles/mental-health-nurses/mental-health-diagnosis-looking-at-a-grey-area-through-a-critical-lens-20-09-2021/
37. Ruffalo ML. A brief history of lithium treatment in psychiatry. Prim Care Companion CNS Disord. 2017;19(5):17br02140.
38. Schizophrenia in children. Boston Children’s Hospital. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.childrenshospital.org/conditions/schizophrenia
39. Villines Z. OCD: related disorders and more. Medical News Today. May 9, 2024. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.medicalnewstoday.com/articles/ocd-related-disorders
40. Reedy J. Panic disorder difficult to diagnose but very treatable. UW News. June 1, 2006. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.washington.edu/news/2006/06/01/panic-disorder-difficult-to-diagnose-but-very-treatable/
41. Mann SK, Marwaha R, Torrico TJ. Posttraumatic stress disorder. StatPearls; 2024.
42. Bipolar disorder. Rethink Mental Illness. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.rethink.org/advice-and-information/about-mental-illness/learn-more-about-conditions/bipolar-disorder/
43. Villines Z. What are the signs of autism in adult men? Medical News Today. July 11, 2023. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.medicalnewstoday.com/articles/signs-of-autism-in-adult-men#main-signs
44. Body dysmorphia symptoms & common side-effects. Timberline Knolls. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://www.timberlineknolls.com/eating-disorder/body-dysmorphia/signs-effects/
45. Wittgenstein L. Wittgenstein Initiative. July 7, 2015. Accessed October 30, 2024. https://wittgenstein-initiative.com/writing-philosophy-as-poetry-literary-form-in-wittgenstein/
For Further Reading
Maj M. Why the clinical utility of diagnostic categories in psychiatry is intrinsically limited and how we can use new approaches to complement them. World Psychiatry. 2018;17(2):121-122.